The (alleged) Normativity Problem


In the course of criticizing those who would appeal to dispositions to answer the sceptical challenge, Kripke makes the following claim:

Suppose I do mean addition by '+'.  What is the relation of this supposition to the question how I will respond to the problem '68 + 57'? The dispositionalist gives a descriptive account of this relation:  if '+' meant addition, then I will answer '125'. But this is not the proper account of the relation, which is normative, not descriptive.  The point is not that, if I meant addition by '+', I will answer '125', but that, if I intend to accord with my past meaning of '+', I should answer '125'.  Computational error, finiteness of my capacity, and other disturbing factors may lead me not to be disposed to respond as I should, but if so, I have not acted in accordance with my intentions.  The relation of meaning and intention to future action is normative, not descriptive.
In the beginning of our discussion of the dispositional analysis, we suggested that it had a certain air of irrelevance with respect to a significant aspect of the sceptical problem -- that the fact that the sceptic can maintain the hypothesis that I meant quus shows that I had no justification for answering '125' rather than '5'.  How does the dispositional analysis even appear to touch this problem?  Our conclusion in the previous paragraph shows that in some sense, after giving a number of more specific criticisms of the dispositional theory, we have returned full circle to our original intuition.  Precisely the fact that our answer to the question of which function I meant is justificatory of my present response is ignored in the dispositional account and leads to all its difficulties. (K, p. 37).

This passage has been hailed by some to contain a great insight about meaning but most importantly, a great insight about what is wrong with appealing to dispositions in order to determine what someone means.  In my commentary on the text, I suggested that there are no such insights to be found here.  On the contrary, the so-called "normativity problem" is not really a problem at all and betrays a confusion on Kripke's part.  The simplest way to bring out the confusion is by appeal to what takes place in translation, including radical translation.

In translation, we begin with someone's signs (syntax) and attribute a meaning (semantics) to his/her signs.  But the meanings so attributed are attributed on the basis of someone's dispositions to use the sign.  (An aside:  If we accept Kripke's case against the appeal to dispositions, we seem to be rejecting Wittgenstein's dictum that meaning is use.  After all, dispositions just are how we use a term, either presently or in the future).   And I agree with Quine that there is really no other way to go about the business of translation other than appeal to dispositions.  So, when we claim, "Jones means plus by '+'", we do so on the basis of Jones' use of '+'.  Clearly, we would make this claim if Jones' use of '+' is in line with '+' meaning addition.

Kripke's sceptic, however, brings up a worry.  He claims that insofar as we confine ourselves to (past?) actual use, we can always find any number of functions which mirror plus or addition on the actual cases in which Jones has used '+', but which differ wildly from plus in cases yet to be considered by Jones.  So for all we can tell, someone who has used '+' in accord with plus so far may not mean plus by '+', but something else (e.g., quus).  Herein is where dispositions come into their own.  Rather than forcing us to confine ourselves to actual uses of '+', we can appeal to Jones' dispositions to use '+' in the future, in "future cases".  If we find that Jones is disposed to say 68 + 57 = 125, 68 + 58 = 126, etc., then we would say, with confidence, that Jones means addition and not quaddition, by '+'.

Now, presumably, Kripke, with his "meaning is normative" slogan, is claiming that there is something illegitimate about this appeal to dispositions to dismiss the sceptic.  But what? The only answer I can find is Kripke's claim above: "  . . . the fact that the sceptic can maintain the hypothesis that I meant quus shows that I had no justification for answering '125' rather than '5'.  How does the dispositional analysis even appear to touch this problem?  . . . Precisely the fact that our answer to the question of which function I meant is justificatory of my present response is ignored in the dispositional account and leads to all its difficulties." (K, p. 37).  Here we see the problem.  The problem is that Kripke has been unfair to the dispositionalist.  For the dispositionalist denies that it is a fact that the sceptic can maintain the hypothesis that Jones meant quus, in the face of Jones having dispositions to go on in accord with addition rather than quaddition.  For Jones' dispositions show which of plus or quus he means.

For related reasons, Kripke is also wrong to claim that dispositionalists "ignore . . . the fact that our answer to the question of which function I meant is justificatory of my present response."  Kripke says this because he thinks that establishing what someone meant/means requires finding something about him/her that shows what s/he should say in some arbitrarily chosen "future" case.  Since dispositionalists tell us only what someone is (actually) disposed to say, they do not, by Kripke's lights, touch the sceptical problem.  Kripke's mistake here is that he misunderstands the relationship between dispositions and the normativity of meaning.  Kripke asks: Is there something about Jones that shows what he should say in particular cases (e.g., 68 + 57)?

Finding that there is nothing to fit this bill (so long as we leave the question of what Jones means open) and in particular, finding that dispositions are of no use in answering this question (since they tell us only what Jones is disposed to say, not what he should say), Kripke concludes that dispositions cannot solve the sceptical problem about what Jones means. But Kripke has started with the wrong "should" question, precisely because he fails to appreciate the force of the dispositional account.  The proper question is as follows: Is Jones disposed to respond as a plusser should?  Unlike Kripke's question, this question is both clear and easily answered (as Kripke himself agrees).  Most importantly, if Jones is disposed to respond as a plusser should, then we are justified to say that Jones means plus.  If not, not.

Once Kripke's mistake is clear, it is clear that Kripke has failed to appreciate the power of the dispositionalist approach.  The power of the dispositional approach to meaning is that it allows us to ask and answer the question of whether Jones is disposed to respond as a plusser should (or as a quusser should, etc.), and thus to answer the question of what Jones means.  This question cannot be raised, let alone answered, so long as we confine ourselves to someone's past answers.  Only the appeal to dispositions allows us to raise the right question about what Jones means, viz., is Jones disposed to use '+' as a plusser (or quusser) should?

As such, Kripke doesn't succeed in showing that dispositions cannot solve the sceptical problem.  At best, he succeeds in showing that without it, without appeal to dispositions, the sceptical problem cannot be solved.

One final thought on all of this.  Although Kripke's claim, "What Jones means is justificatory of Jones' present response", appears innocuous enough, it masks a confusion.  One problem with Kripke's claim is that it suggests that Jones' "present response", as well as any "present responses" yet to come, cannot be used in a determination of Jones' meaning.  For Kripke clearly holds that we must first determine what Jones means in order to be able to say what Jones should say in the present case, which of course, constitutes a justification of Jones' present response.  For Kripke, if Jones' meaning depends on his present response, Jones' meaning cannot be justificatory of that response.  But it should be clear from the above that Kripke is off base.  Whether Jones means one thing rather than another by '+' is to be determined by looking at Jones' dispositions to use '+'.  And once we know what Jones means by '+', we can see whether his present response is justified, given that meaning.  That is, we can say that since Jones means plus by '+', 125 is a correct and so justified response to 68 + 57.  And since he means plus, 5 is an incorrect and so unjustified response to 68 + 57.

Of course, nothing prevents Jones, a la Humpty Dumpty, from altering his use of '+'.  As such, Jones could justify giving any answer he likes to 68 + 57, so long as he was willing to change his use of '+', i.e., willing to change his dispositions to use '+'.  So, Jones can justify saying, 68 + 57 = 5, only by saying that he is not plussing.  The upshot then is that justification of a response by meaning requires saying what the meaning is, e.g., that Jones means plus, or Jones means quus, etc.  It is illegitimate to speak of justification of a present response by meaning simpliciter.  Kripke seems to me to be guilty of this mistake in this part of his text.


Top of Page | WRPL Ultimate HomePage


Last modified October 3, 2011
JAH, Professor
Dept. of Philosophy